4.36 |
The objection may be raised that telling stories is not
reasoning, not objectifying the world. The point
here is that knowledge production of whatever sort
passes through social relations. There is no
unmediated access to a world. Access, by
participation or by detachment, involves power.
|
4.36 |
4.37 |
In situations where the ethical argument holds, where
appeals are made to the character of a speaker or
interpreter, be they in book-learning or oral cultures,
mnemonic devices are never very far from the person of
the knowledge producers, the epistemic
interlocutors. Such tools are important
attributes of all persons involved. Havelock's
lone rhapsode may equally be controlled by collective
constraints. Indeed his account by stressing
agonistic features acknowledges the claims of counter-
memories.
|
4.37 |
4.38 |
Just as counter-memories imply counter-narratives or in
less polarized accounts, variations, the paradigm
stories of psychoanalytic discourse itself are subject
to variant readings of its own condensations and
displacements, its own dreamwork tropes. A space
is opened for rhetorical analysis.
|
4.38 |
4.39 |
The Oedipal paradigm centres on the acquisition of
language. It matters little if separation anxiety
as postulated by object relations theory precedes or
follows the achievement of linguistic ability. In
one case it is a reaction, a result; in the other,
motive or cause. Language is like a fence against
denied psychic content or like a knife cutting off the
repressed content, instituting the denial. These
similes highlight the axiomatic status within object
relations theory of an instrumental concept of
language. Object relations theory itself does not
employ these similies of knife or fence. In
psychoanalytic narratives of separation anxiety or
stories of castration menace, language does
things. Language acquisiton is comparable to the
grasping of a tool to cut and contain. But
language is also done.
|
4.39 |
4.40 |
Language as material product is worked upon.
Language is practised. Language also refers to
the site where practices and products meet.
Technical vocabularies attempt to control this
polysemy. For example, the structuralist
terminology of language, langue and
parole corresponds to faculty, rules
and acts of expression. These distinctions work
well in considering the relation of system to
performance. They work well in theorizing the
actualization of potentials. They offer points of
departure and arrival.
|
4.40 |
4.41 |
They do not alleviate tendencies to conflate place and
means when language is considered as a medium.
The conflation is inevitable. A place is a
means. Places are prepared. Wisdom of
sacred sites. The uncanny energy of domestic
arrangements. The house of language. The
analogies are potent and have consequences for thinking
language's relation to the body.
|
4.41 |
4.42 |
If language is a tool for the fashioning of self and
the construction of an other, it is the body and its
zones that facilitate the entry into language. Is
the body, this means to an end, a tool? An
instrument upon which the infant plays? A
tantalizing alignment ensues: text as
instrument, text as infant.
|
4.42 |
4.43 |
The jump from language to text through those teasing
unvoiced dentals and their alliteration
(text tantalizing
infant instrument) issues
from the seduction of the signifier. Already the
rearrangement implies text as agent of a pleasurable
irritation, on the infant-instrument, of the infant-
instrument, in the infant-instrument. The
difficulty in ascribing a preposition matches the
difficulty of ascribing agency: the text?
the infant?
|
4.43 |
4.44 |
With Flax is reached the limit of the infant as
patient. With Bordo, the limit of the agency of
the instrument. It is the limit of insertion that
guides Dorothy Smith's discourse. Unlike the
feminists inspired by psychoanalysis, Smith does not
invoke interiorization as a developmental
mechanism. In fact, her standpoint epistemology
is not developmental. However the dynamics of
inside/outside structuration shape her claim for the
suppression of bodily consciousness upon entry into the
"abstracted conceptual mode".
|
4.44 |
4.45 |
Following Marx and Engels, in particular The
German Ideology, Smith relates consciousness to
what people do, not what they are. The social
division of labour places constraints on action and
hence on consciousness. The ways people think
about and express themselves depend upon their
embeddedness in an everyday world. When Smith
grafts phenomenological sociology on to this
materialist base, her analyses shift towards
meditations on spheres of activity. Consciousness
becomes spatialized. One enters a cognitive
mode. As well she also situates both practices of
knowledge production and spheres of activity in a
sexual division of labour.
|
4.45 |
4.46 |
Grossly, her argument depends upon a mapping of private
and public space onto physical and conceptual activity
respectively. This mapping is mediated by an
implicit reading of social reproduction as woman's work
and management or ruling as men's. Women by
analogy are in a position similar to the working class
(n9). The
limits of the analogy remain unexplored. When she
further argues that the arrangement's perpetuation
depends upon its unacknowledgement by those whom it
benefits, that is, the ruling class, her epistemology,
like that of psychoanalytic feminists, hinges upon
repression as a prerequisite for abstract reasoning.
|
4.46 |
4.47 |
Although she makes no explicit reference to the
difference between class consciousness and class
analysis, between knowing one's place in a system and
knowing the system, it is such a distinction that
informs her assessment of material and conceptual
labour as epistemological stances. The values she
assigns are of course informed by considerations of
gender. What she calls acting in the
"abstracted conceptual mode" is associated
with ruling. The physical labour that supports
this mode is "done typically by women" (Smith 1977, 165). The one is
ignorant; the other, all-knowing.
|
4.47 |