4.17 |
Taking up Flax's points one notes that difficulties in
screening, sorting or modifying experience also happen
in verbal behaviour. It is not a set of
activities that is mastered once and for all.
Recognition of this would challenge Flax's topography
of the ego.
|
4.17 |
4.18 |
Indeed, elsewhere in the same text she assumes
similarities between verbal and preverbal stages.
There is a slippage in Flax's text from
"infancy", "infantile drama" to
"child" and "child within" (247). Infantile and childhood
memories, the child elements of the ego, are deemed
repressed and difficult to access. They are
inside. They are cathected to internalized
objects. Intrinsic to this stress on
internalization is an equation of repression with a
"keeping in" rather than a "keeping
from". What does this entail for the place
of reason?
|
4.18 |
4.19 |
The characterization of the infant as prerational explains the difficulties in processing experience. However the equation between reason and language contradicts the innateness of reason posited earlier in Flax's text. As she points out, object relations theory is itself a questioning of Freud's instinct theory (n4) and the place of reason within his theory. Object relations theory according to Flax sees reason as an innate potential capacity rather than a faculty painfully acquired through the internalization of the authority of the father and as defense against frustration and threats from the external world. (249)
If reasoning capacity is innate, how can the infant's
engagement with experience be prerational? The
potential capacity can be activated before the
acquisition of verbal skills. Indeed it must be
for those skills to be acquired.
|
4.19 |
4.20 |
The preservation of an inner prerational core depends
finally upon the marginalization of intense
experiences. Flax claims religious and
hallucinogenic experiences occur rarely. It
seems, for her, erotic activity registers no
intensity. If however one considers that
experience is constructed and in a constant state of
construction then its handling poses problems not only
for the infant who is a being in a state of verbal
impotency but also for adept language users.
Intense difficulty in sorting, modifying or screening
tasks that construct experience
are also the lot of reading
subjects. From Flax one does reach for intriguing
metaphors. As a child before the text, the reader
is demanding, querying. As an infant before the
text? The parental analogy reaches a
limit. Objects bob in a force field of
drives. Zones.
|
4.20 |
4.21 |
These metaphors play with the distinction between the
speaking child and the extra-linguistic infant and do
introduce the drives of Freudian theory. Of
course, the mother is not a text. However the
comparison has heuristic value. The reading
subject's relation to a text is best not patterned on a
one-to-one dyad. Memories of other texts hover
and the reading subject is traversed by competing
desires. Field faces field.
|
4.21 |
4.22 |
Likewise the developing human's relation to sources of
nurture or the human's consciousness of those sources
need not, on empirical or conceptual grounds, be
theorized as dyadic. Since an ideology of the
couple is basic to object relations theory, it is
forced to assume separation in terms of break-up.
Thus the developmental stage of recognizing objects as
independent of the self, the stage when the infant
recognizes that temporally discrete percepts may
constitute apprehension of the same object, the stage
at which the mother emerges as a distinct object,
produces anxiety. Only anxiety. There is no
possibility for cognitive joy.
|
4.22 |
4.23 |
The game of losing and finding the object of desire is
in object relations theory a stage that breaks up the
blissful dyad. Divorce is traumatic. But
equally so for both parties? Posited in the
theories drawn upon by Flax and her intellectual heirs
is the essential unity of infant self. That unity
confirms the status of identification as a key category
in gender role formation and authorizes interiorization
of the infantile drama. The preeminence of
identification and interiorization is a consequence of
the reification of the couple. The reliance on
dyads becomes even more perplexing when explanations
move from individual to collective development.
|
4.23 |
4.24 |
In Flight to Objectivity, Susan Bordo
extrapolates from the ontogenic story of individual
human development offered by object relations theory to
phylogenic explanation of changes in historical
consciousness. The psychocultural history
outlined by Bordo rests upon two coordinations.
As in object relations theory, a relation to one's body
is embroiled in a relation to one's mother. It is
also through this nexus that one's relation to the
world passes.
|
4.24 |
4.25 |
For Bordo the gendering of nature is considered in universal rather than historical terms. She accepts a mapping of the physical world unto the figure of the mother. This allows a second coordination between the rise of the scientific method and denial of separation anxiety. Since a cognitive style is coordinated with a developmental theory, Bordo can characterize the rise of modern science as a turning away from the maternal body towards the paternal mind: The change may also be described in terms of separation from the maternal the immanent realm of earth, nature, the authority of the body and a compensatory turning toward the paternal for legitimation through external regulation, transcendent values, and the authority of law. [original emphasis] (Bordo 58) |
4.25 |
4.26 |
The mind-body opposition is left intact.
Moreover, when Bordo's stress on the gendering of the
opposition is amalgamated with the psychological
defense mechanisms against separation anxiety, she opts
for a narrative which terminates in the exemplary dream
of knowledge "imagined as an explicit revenge
fantasy, an attempt to wrest back control from
nature" (Bordo 75). The
concentration on power struggles is vivid but not
accurate. Bordo chooses to focus on a single
defense mechanism. She explicitly recognizes that
psychoanalytic theory has described three responses to
separation from the mother (Bordo
106). They are denial,
longing and mourning.
|
4.26 |
4.27 |
It is possible to maintain the reading of ontogenic separation anxiety onto a phylogenic frame, without privileging the response of denial. For example, Jacquelyn N. Zita, in a review of Bordo's book, refers to work by Genevieve Lloyd and proposes a different conjecture: The ontological separation of mind from body could thus be seen as a way of making physical differences between the sexes less significant and asserting the equality of the sexes in rationality and will. (Zita 647)
With this interpretation of dualism, Zita does not
demonize Descartes. She considers biographical
elements, his epistolary exchanges with women, the
early death of his mother, and his decision to write in
the vernacular (few women read Latin). Descartes
is figured as a creature of longing. Bordo
nowhere tackles the ambiguities in the Cartesian
corpus. She mentions Lloyd only once, in
passing. The mention is subsumed in a list of
other names (Bordo 4). To move
beyond a dyad, she would have to account for the role
of sisters and other siblings, as well as mothers in
the development of individual and collective
consciousness.
|
4.27 |