4.0 |
The discursive formations exemplified by the classic
eye-ear case such as dichotomous categorizations,
frozen hierarchies, and cyclic reversals lose
legitimacy if mind and body are considered as mutually
interactive. Recursivity, especially in its
cybernetic manifestations, provides an analogy for that
interaction. It also provides a discursive
mechanism that can generate rhetorical moves that do
not pit hearing against sight or slight other sensory
modalites.
|
4.0 |
4.1 |
Recursivity marks the relation of mind and body:
to know, to be a body that knows, to be a body that
knows its knowing. From successive recursivity,
dialectic, the possibility of reasoning, the potential
for asking questions, emerges. The leap from
recursivity to dialectic is managed by three
premises. First, the body is a medium. It
is material, tool and repository of repertoire
(habit). Second, sensory modalities are open to
transcoding. Such transcoding is related to
powers of abstraction. Third, nondyadic models of
embodied consciousness and text handling best explain
conceptual play and discursive practice. The key
in this cursory and condensed precis is, of course,
sensory transcoding. It permits one to model the
thinking body by analogy with textual interaction and
account for the semiotic intersection of different ways
of knowing.
|
4.1 |
4.2 |
Using the analogy between the relation of reading
subjects to texts and the relation of thinking bodies
to themselves one can profitably reread Ricoeur's
notion of appropriation and Ingarden's, of
concretization. With the analogy between a
thinking body's relation to itself and a text's
relation to a reading subject, the theorizing of text
handling becomes less embroiled in sensory bias.
Likewise the excavation of sensory bias in some
versions of feminist epistemology aids the exploration
of embodied consciousness. The exercise aims to
discover discursive repressions and limitations that
impinge on the imagining of thinking, feeling subjects.
|
4.2 |
4.3 |
The names that follow are rarely uttered in the same
breath. Less rarely, they are found in the same
library. Dorothy Smith's cartography of the modes
of consciousness is cousin to the phenomenological
literary aesthetics of Roman Ingarden. Susan
Bordo and Jane Flax share a common intellectual
heritage with the hermeneutics of Paul Ricoeur.
He and they draw on psychoanalysis. He, for his
notion of appropriation; they, in
conceptualizing repression of maternal bond and the
role of detachment in intellectual activity. All
the thinkers gathered here are golden fodder for
critique but they are not entirely made of pale yellow
straw. All slight in some fashion either the body
or the mind. To do one or the other is to neglect
the social aspects of technology, perception and
reproduction. Indeed theoretical consideration of
this nexus depends upon privileging neither mind nor
body. Furthermore, placing body and mind on par
amounts to accepting both mental and bodily experience
as social and rational.
|
4.3 |
4.4 |
The genesis of ways of knowing is entangled with
intellectual and erotic ways of being. In some
languages, the intellectual and the erotic share the
verb "to know". Often the struggle to
disentangle sexuality from biological reproduction has
been characterized by the adversaries of feminist
positions as the imposition of reason on nature.
This argument also plays a role in the
conceptualization of the relation of technology to
perception. This is the case for McLuhan.
Ironically, the same argument, reason dominating
nature, inflects certain feminist epistemologies.
In some cases, social reproduction veers deterministic
when sexuality is not sufficiently distinguished from
biological reproduction. Such discourse has
difficulty articulating homosocial let alone homosexual
phenomena. Investigations are limited to cross-
gender interaction.
|
4.4 |
4.5 |
However mere attention to same-sex interactions without
a radical requestioning of the centrality of dyads
would be no guarantee against the recurrence of
dispositional explanations and the spectre of
determinism. Such dichotomizing feminist work
seeks "to explain why objectivity as detachment
and noninvolvement is the epistemological stance to
which men are predisposed" (Arnault
204 n. 7). The work
rests on the construction
of a pathologized target. This is possible
because a dichotomous category of participation
(involvement and non-involvement) is positioned within
a polarized relation of gender and valence: men and
women; bad and good. Truth-values aside, accounts
based on the construction of predispositions remain
unreflexive.
|
4.5 |
4.6 |
This pattern is not representative of all feminist epistemologies. Stanley and Wise interrogate the relation between theory and experience within the production of feminist knowledge. Their epistemology comes out of dialogues within British feminism. They develop their work partially in response to their own experience of Marxist-feminist currents within British academic feminism. Perhaps since they do not target an entity called Cartesianism, they avoid adopting dualist formulations. For them positivism and scientificism are not the sole preserve of men. They stress differences between women as much as those between men and women. They refuse to pathologize even the oppressor class. A feminist developmental theory that can explain neither feminism nor difference between groups of women (and men) except as the product of malfunctioning should be anathema to feminists [...] (Stanley and Wise 1993, 7)
Consequently their epistemology can not bolster moral
superiority or nostalgic longing for an integrated body
and mind. In their thinking, theory is an
activity. It is of the domain of practice.
Mind-body relations are constructed out of social
interaction. This primacy of the social ensures
that in their discourse mere reversal is never lodged
as a fulcrum, never left unquestioned.
|
4.6 |
4.7 |
The ethnomethodological and interactionist-inspired
work of Stanley and Wise does not find a place in the
typology of feminist epistemologies offered by Lynne
Arnault. All the various thinkers she groups
together are said to be concerned with masculine
predisposition to "objectivity as detachment and
noninvolvement". Within this common design,
Arnault explains that "some feminists make
recourse to feminist revisions of "object-
relations" theory. [...] Less
psychoanalytically oriented feminists account for the
gender specificity of the Cartesian ideal in terms of a
post-Marxist theory of labour and its effects upon
mental life" (Arnault
204). Of her examples,
Susan Bordo and Jane
Flax are users of object relations, Dorothy Smith, a
user of labour theories. These thinkers will draw
closer examination.
|
4.7 |
4.8 |
Compared to the work of Stanley and Wise, the feminist
theory represented in Arnault's typology suffers.
Stanley and Wise are very sensitive to the power of the
telling of stories. Despite psychoanalysis being
a discipline devoted to the interpretation of
narratives, Bordo and Flax do not display in the
deployment of their tales such self-reflexivity.
|
4.8 |
4.9 |
Likewise in reference to the worlds generated by
discourses, the epistemology of Stanley and Wise will
not privilege access to an unmediated objective
world. Their discussion of Popper's three world
model for example makes this clear (n1).
Smith's standpoint epistemology evolves out of
responses to the phenomenological sociology of Alfred
Schutz, responses that can be read as a reversal of the
hierarchal relation between Schutz's categories of
paramount reality and scientific domain. Measured
against Stanley and Wise, Smith's epistemology would
appear insufficiently dialectical, insufficiently
prepared to begin again.
|
4.9 |
4.10 |
Obviously, the present comparative examination esteems
dialectical thinking and self-reflexivity as positive
values. It is a bias. A style.
|
4.10 |
4.11 |
Let us see what it can do. Following Patricia Meyer Spacks on Simone de Beauvoir and masculine standards of accomplishment (Spacks 19), Stanley and Wise state: We are uncomfortably aware that similar remarks can and should be levelled at our own style of presentation and mode of argument, as well as that of many other feminist writers. Words, sentences, writing styles, ways of presenting arguments, arguments themselves, criticism, all these are part and parcel of masculinist culture. They are among the artefacts of sexism, and their use structures our experience before we can even begin to examine it, because they provide with how we think as well as how we write. We are in a circle [...] Of course it isn't quite like this. The social world is neither so determinate nor so relentlessly sexist as this but that it is presented as such is an important feature of the means by which sexism is perpetuated. (Stanley and Wise 1993, 179)
Fears of contamination bred from an us-them division of
discursive property, a simply bipartisan distribution
of the terms and styles of argmentation can hamper the
transfer of critical theory into political
action. As the example of Stanley and Wise
demonstrates, dialectical thinking potentially
generates complication. At every turn, inertia,
set ideas, frozen interpretative frames are
eluded. Yet, paradoxically the mind's movement
can question the goodness of overcoming inertia.
The value of recursivity is radically contextual.
|
4.11 |
4.12 |
Dialectic is not a forte of other feminists. Determinism and dyads mark analyses like those of Jane Flax that stem from Nancy Chodorow's The Reproduction of Mothering. The latter's position has been caricatured as blaming the mother for the production of sexism. One easily reads such deterministic stances from her text, if one is not careful to remark that parenting and its ideological constructs are only claimed as one site of struggle among others: An ideology of women as mothers extends to women's responsibilities as maternal wives for emotional reconstitution and support of their working husbands. Assumptions that the social organization of parenting is natural and proper (that women's child care is indistinguishable from their childbearing, that women are for biological reasons better parents than men, moral arguments that women ought to mother) have continued to serve as grounds for arguments against most changes in the social organization of gender. ( Chodorow 219)
The text in its use of plural forms intimates that
there may be other grounds for the articulation of the
resistance to change. For example, the sartorial
industries, the producers of wedding gowns and sex
trade accoutrements, certainly do not advocate
restructuring the social organization of gender.
Attitudes towards parenting are not an explain-all and
Chodorow never claims to build a totalizing theory.
|
4.12 |
4.13 |
Ironically, deterministic postures in their psychoanalytic guise evolve from Chodorow's account. This is the case of Jane Flax. She focuses on the male child's relation to the mother to produce a single narrative of separation. It is a narrative where she emphasizes the inevitability of the developmental outcome: He must become male. In order to do so he must become not female, since under patriarchy gender is an exclusionary category. [original emphasis] (Flax 246)
Absent here are a differentiation between gender and
sex or an acknowledgement that patriarchy (n2) under
capitalism is very pliant (Gender roles often shift in
war economies). Note under patriarchy in Flax's
version man becomes, woman is. Flax's account
seems to replicate the existence of an eternal
feminine used to define historical male
subjectivity. How then will patriarchy be
dismantled? The solution rests on the alignment
of several psychoanalytic postulates: the
eternal-feminine-coupled-to-male-subjectivity structure
depends upon the repression on the part of men of
infantile dependence and since this repression is
equivalent to an investment of frustrated energies in
the figure of the mother which is then cast out and
since any woman can signify the mother figure, the
structure will be dissolved when men cease repressing
feelings of dependence and powerlessness, cease
investing energy in figures to be cast away and cease
reading all women as incarnations of the Mother
figure. Baldly stated the argument suggests that
if men did not grow up, they would not demonize
women. The argument rests on shakey universal
premises: all women are mothers; all men desire
mothers. One might perhaps recognize here the
twin premises of heteronormativity.
Psychoanalytic convolutions aside, even an unanxious
relation to parent figures is no guarantee against
adoption of a cognitive style to which someone
somewhere will object because it appears to lack
emotion in its commitment to reason.
|
4.13 |
4.14 |
When the repression thesis is applied to the adoption
of cognitive styles difficulties arise. Flax asks
what is repressed in philosophical discourse. She
invokes the Oedipal plot and its outcome, the
repression of dependence and powerlessness, to find
that philosophical discourse represses "the
interactive character of early human development"
(251). The connection is not
clear unless one fantasizes that the boys doing
philosophy are liable to feel threatened if they
recognize interaction (read "involvement"
according to Arnault's typology) as a valid
philosophical topic or as an important factor in
philosophical exchange.
|
4.14 |
4.15 |
The existence of philosophers of the male gender who
discuss emotion and cognition, reason and passion, in
non-exclusive terms before feminist critiques became
widespread leads one to question how
"philosophy" is constructed in Flax's
discourse (n3). It is telling that her analyses
are organized by name not by theme. This is not
attachment to the names of the fathers. This is
the discursive practice of case studies. They
deal with lives not bodies.
|
4.15 |
4.16 |
The use of case studies presents the problem of induction. However Flax's mode is not one of generalization from particulars. The case studies illustrate theory. They do not generate or modify theory. Within her psychoanalytic framework, case studies have no impact on theory. Every case is a life. Every life is marked by the same crescendo organised along the dynamics of the Oedipal plot. In Flax this is marked by the attribution of unsurpassed intensity to infancy: This period [infancy] is marked not only by physical and emotional dependency but by an intensity of experience which will never be repeated except in psychosis and perhaps in altered states of consciousness such as religious or drug experiences. Precisely because it is prerational and preverbal, it is difficult for the infant to screen, sort and modify its experience. (Flax 254)
In this paragraph Flax juxtaposes three elements:
infant difficulty displayed in handling
experience; equation of reason and
language; marginalization of intense
experience. Flax seems unaware that altered
states of consciousness are mightily repeatable.
Furthermore, a bit of dialectical thinking would force
a bit of modification in the relation of adults to
childhood experience. Questioning the distinction
between altered and non-altered states invites a
reassessment of margin and infant and the intensity
ascribed to them.
|
4.16 |
4.17 |
Taking up Flax's points one notes that difficulties in
screening, sorting or modifying experience also happen
in verbal behaviour. It is not a set of
activities that is mastered once and for all.
Recognition of this would challenge Flax's topography
of the ego.
|
4.17 |
4.18 |
Indeed, elsewhere in the same text she assumes
similarities between verbal and preverbal stages.
There is a slippage in Flax's text from
"infancy", "infantile drama" to
"child" and "child within" (247). Infantile and childhood
memories, the child elements of the ego, are deemed
repressed and difficult to access. They are
inside. They are cathected to internalized
objects. Intrinsic to this stress on
internalization is an equation of repression with a
"keeping in" rather than a "keeping
from". What does this entail for the place
of reason?
|
4.18 |
4.19 |
The characterization of the infant as prerational explains the difficulties in processing experience. However the equation between reason and language contradicts the innateness of reason posited earlier in Flax's text. As she points out, object relations theory is itself a questioning of Freud's instinct theory (n4) and the place of reason within his theory. Object relations theory according to Flax sees reason as an innate potential capacity rather than a faculty painfully acquired through the internalization of the authority of the father and as defense against frustration and threats from the external world. (249)
If reasoning capacity is innate, how can the infant's
engagement with experience be prerational? The
potential capacity can be activated before the
acquisition of verbal skills. Indeed it must be
for those skills to be acquired.
|
4.19 |
4.20 |
The preservation of an inner prerational core depends
finally upon the marginalization of intense
experiences. Flax claims religious and
hallucinogenic experiences occur rarely. It
seems, for her, erotic activity registers no
intensity. If however one considers that
experience is constructed and in a constant state of
construction then its handling poses problems not only
for the infant who is a being in a state of verbal
impotency but also for adept language users.
Intense difficulty in sorting, modifying or screening
tasks that construct experience
are also the lot of reading
subjects. From Flax one does reach for intriguing
metaphors. As a child before the text, the reader
is demanding, querying. As an infant before the
text? The parental analogy reaches a
limit. Objects bob in a force field of
drives. Zones.
|
4.20 |
4.21 |
These metaphors play with the distinction between the
speaking child and the extra-linguistic infant and do
introduce the drives of Freudian theory. Of
course, the mother is not a text. However the
comparison has heuristic value. The reading
subject's relation to a text is best not patterned on a
one-to-one dyad. Memories of other texts hover
and the reading subject is traversed by competing
desires. Field faces field.
|
4.21 |
4.22 |
Likewise the developing human's relation to sources of
nurture or the human's consciousness of those sources
need not, on empirical or conceptual grounds, be
theorized as dyadic. Since an ideology of the
couple is basic to object relations theory, it is
forced to assume separation in terms of break-up.
Thus the developmental stage of recognizing objects as
independent of the self, the stage when the infant
recognizes that temporally discrete percepts may
constitute apprehension of the same object, the stage
at which the mother emerges as a distinct object,
produces anxiety. Only anxiety. There is no
possibility for cognitive joy.
|
4.22 |
4.23 |
The game of losing and finding the object of desire is
in object relations theory a stage that breaks up the
blissful dyad. Divorce is traumatic. But
equally so for both parties? Posited in the
theories drawn upon by Flax and her intellectual heirs
is the essential unity of infant self. That unity
confirms the status of identification as a key category
in gender role formation and authorizes interiorization
of the infantile drama. The preeminence of
identification and interiorization is a consequence of
the reification of the couple. The reliance on
dyads becomes even more perplexing when explanations
move from individual to collective development.
|
4.23 |
4.24 |
In Flight to Objectivity, Susan Bordo
extrapolates from the ontogenic story of individual
human development offered by object relations theory to
phylogenic explanation of changes in historical
consciousness. The psychocultural history
outlined by Bordo rests upon two coordinations.
As in object relations theory, a relation to one's body
is embroiled in a relation to one's mother. It is
also through this nexus that one's relation to the
world passes.
|
4.24 |
4.25 |
For Bordo the gendering of nature is considered in universal rather than historical terms. She accepts a mapping of the physical world unto the figure of the mother. This allows a second coordination between the rise of the scientific method and denial of separation anxiety. Since a cognitive style is coordinated with a developmental theory, Bordo can characterize the rise of modern science as a turning away from the maternal body towards the paternal mind: The change may also be described in terms of separation from the maternal the immanent realm of earth, nature, the authority of the body and a compensatory turning toward the paternal for legitimation through external regulation, transcendent values, and the authority of law. [original emphasis] (Bordo 58) |
4.25 |
4.26 |
The mind-body opposition is left intact.
Moreover, when Bordo's stress on the gendering of the
opposition is amalgamated with the psychological
defense mechanisms against separation anxiety, she opts
for a narrative which terminates in the exemplary dream
of knowledge "imagined as an explicit revenge
fantasy, an attempt to wrest back control from
nature" (Bordo 75). The
concentration on power struggles is vivid but not
accurate. Bordo chooses to focus on a single
defense mechanism. She explicitly recognizes that
psychoanalytic theory has described three responses to
separation from the mother (Bordo
106). They are denial,
longing and mourning.
|
4.26 |
4.27 |
It is possible to maintain the reading of ontogenic separation anxiety onto a phylogenic frame, without privileging the response of denial. For example, Jacquelyn N. Zita, in a review of Bordo's book, refers to work by Genevieve Lloyd and proposes a different conjecture: The ontological separation of mind from body could thus be seen as a way of making physical differences between the sexes less significant and asserting the equality of the sexes in rationality and will. (Zita 647)
With this interpretation of dualism, Zita does not
demonize Descartes. She considers biographical
elements, his epistolary exchanges with women, the
early death of his mother, and his decision to write in
the vernacular (few women read Latin). Descartes
is figured as a creature of longing. Bordo
nowhere tackles the ambiguities in the Cartesian
corpus. She mentions Lloyd only once, in
passing. The mention is subsumed in a list of
other names (Bordo 4). To move
beyond a dyad, she would have to account for the role
of sisters and other siblings, as well as mothers in
the development of individual and collective
consciousness.
|
4.27 |
4.28 |
Related to the lack of consideration for intra-
generational or horizontal relationships is a
presumption that the past is a parent. Medieval
mother confronts the scientific age father. The
neglect of theology leads Bordo to favour epistemic
breaks over continuities. Even a strong adherence
to a narrative of rupture does not preclude some
problems in periodization. For example, the
medieval period itself can be the point at which
separation anxiety arises. This is a feasible
scenario if, forgetting about charitable care of thy
neighbour's body, Christian mortification of the flesh
is compared to a previous pagan era's putative
celebration of the body and of nature.
|
4.38 |
4.29 |
In the familial drama approach to history, any event
can be interpreted as result or as motive. Not
all emplotment is caricature. For example, the
rise of the scientific method can be read within the
context of a reaction to the wars of religion (Toulmin). The entertaining of
counter arguments and alternative narratives is
facilitated if historical periods are not personified
as parents.
|
4.29 |
4.30 |
Despite a tendency to homogenize historical periods, Bordo is not a total zeitgeist enthusiast. An inkling of the concept of hegemony appears in her discourse when her psychocultural account grafts developments in the visual arts onto changes in the conception of space. The evidence may point to another story. Bordo claims it is only after the conventionalization of linear perspective in art and, according to Karsten Harries and others, largely as a result of its influence that the homogeneous, infinite space "implied" in the perspective painting becomes the "official" space of the culture. (Bordo 68) In the note to this section of Flight to Objectivity, the "others" represent only one other source (n5). Furthermore, in the article cited by Bordo, Harries suggests Rhenish mysticism and hermetic tradition as other possible factors (Harries 31 n. 1) and announces a forthcoming treatment of these in a study on Nicolaus Cusanus. In this later article ignored by Bordo his position is clear: It would be misleading to place too much weight on this reflection, which leads from a consideration of perspective to the infinity of the cosmos. (Harries 1975, 7) Harries unlike Bordo discusses the matter in terms of correlation rather than causation: Historically and conceptually central perspective, which was given its theoretical foundation by Brunelleschi and Alberti, and the objective space of the new science are closely related forms of description. (Harries 1975, 7)
"Closely related forms" of description
suggests a complex genealogy. Other possible
influences, such as the Kabbalah, on the development of
the idea of infinite space are traced by Max Jammer (n6) whose
complementary study seems unknown to Harries at the
time of the appearance of these articles.
|
4.30 |
4.31 |
For Harries art is only one locus, one expression, for
"the rising awareness of and interest in the
phenomenon of perspective [...] that goes hand
in hand with the emergence of the objective conception
of space which is presupposed by the new science"
(Harries 1973, 30). The wide
currency gained by speculations on the nature of
perspective is adduced by a circa 1530 Nuremburg
woodcut which indicates that the "sixteenth
century was ready for the discoveries of Tycho Brahe
and Galileo" (31). Harries
describes the figure in the illustration as
"breaking out of the shell of the cosmos" (31). Bordo no doubt was seized
by
his ekphrasis.
|
4.31 |
4.32 |
The evidence offered can alternatively be taken to
illustrate the question of Archytas who asked whether
it would be possible at the end of the world to stretch
out one's hand or not. This ancient philosopher's
challenge to the Aristotelian cosmology is preserved in
a commentary on the Physics by
Simplicius. Reservations about circulation of
early manuscripts and of thirteenth century Latin
translations notwithstanding, the commentary became,
just prior to the period in question, widely
current. In 1526, four years before the date
attributed to the Nuremburg woodcut, is published by
the Aldine press in Venice an edition of
Simplicius. Four years is enough time for story
or book to cover the distance, an engraver to work,
proofs be pulled, yet not too much time to elapse
before discounting any possible direct connection or
influence. However, the common Renaissance
practice of using the same illustration for different
texts mitigates against conclusive
interpretations.
|
4.32 |
4.33 |
Nonetheless, the printing press does play a role in the rise of ideas about infinite space as much as it does in the circulation and production of any intellectual property. It is not however a necessary cause except perhaps in a tale of detachment. And so Bordo claims: the ability to "discover reality" in the perspective painting requires visual skills the ability to adopt a detached point of view and to scan a static frame that are developed, McLuhan argues, only through experience at silent, private reading of the printed page. (Bordo 66)
One would have thought that the experience of trying to
draw would teach one about how to see. Bordo
uncritically adopts McLuhan's assumption of universal
literacy and thus disregards collective viewing
accompanied by oral commentary as a means of passing on
the visual skills necessary for the appreciation of
perspectival painting. McLuhan's eye-ear
dichotomy serves to authorize not only Bordo's spacial
categorization of cognitive activity into private
detached and participatory public but also her
privileging of participation over detachment (n7).
|
4.33 |
4.34 |
Regardless of the validity of the medium/message
collapse, participation in its various guises (n8) does not
curry full favour with all of Bordo's sources.
Enumerating several writers, she enlists their
authority to claim that "The subject/object
distinction has, at the very least,
hardened over time" (Bordo 48). One of her sources
patently says the opposite. Owen Barfield credits
modern physical science and philosophy since Kant for
recognizing participation of the human mind in the
creation or evocation of the phenomena of the familiar
world (Barfield 12).
|
4.34 |
4.35 |
She quotes from Morris Berman who describing a break in
ancient Greek epistemology summarizes Eric Havelock's
work (Bordo 48; Berman
71). She does not apply
herself to Havelock's
work directly. She does not recognize that the
ethics of instrumentality are no purer in cultures
governed by participation. Havelock writes:
"To control the collective memory of society he
[the reciter] had to establish control over the
personal memories of individual human beings" (Havelock 145). To this effect,
Havelock makes note of Marcel Jousse's description of
verbomoteurs, the inhabitants of oral
cultures, as mnemotechnicians. As evidenced by
Havelock's and Jousse's instrumental vocabulary,
technocratic motives are observer-dependent.
Equally so
are observations on contact with a maternal
realm. Approached from the pole of performance,
participatory cultures are far from bonding with the
mother. Participatory cultures have their own
technologies.
|
4.35 |
4.36 |
The objection may be raised that telling stories is not
reasoning, not objectifying the world. The point
here is that knowledge production of whatever sort
passes through social relations. There is no
unmediated access to a world. Access, by
participation or by detachment, involves power.
|
4.36 |
4.37 |
In situations where the ethical argument holds, where
appeals are made to the character of a speaker or
interpreter, be they in book-learning or oral cultures,
mnemonic devices are never very far from the person of
the knowledge producers, the epistemic
interlocutors. Such tools are important
attributes of all persons involved. Havelock's
lone rhapsode may equally be controlled by collective
constraints. Indeed his account by stressing
agonistic features acknowledges the claims of counter-
memories.
|
4.37 |
4.38 |
Just as counter-memories imply counter-narratives or in
less polarized accounts, variations, the paradigm
stories of psychoanalytic discourse itself are subject
to variant readings of its own condensations and
displacements, its own dreamwork tropes. A space
is opened for rhetorical analysis.
|
4.38 |
4.39 |
The Oedipal paradigm centres on the acquisition of
language. It matters little if separation anxiety
as postulated by object relations theory precedes or
follows the achievement of linguistic ability. In
one case it is a reaction, a result; in the other,
motive or cause. Language is like a fence against
denied psychic content or like a knife cutting off the
repressed content, instituting the denial. These
similes highlight the axiomatic status within object
relations theory of an instrumental concept of
language. Object relations theory itself does not
employ these similies of knife or fence. In
psychoanalytic narratives of separation anxiety or
stories of castration menace, language does
things. Language acquisiton is comparable to the
grasping of a tool to cut and contain. But
language is also done.
|
4.39 |
4.40 |
Language as material product is worked upon.
Language is practised. Language also refers to
the site where practices and products meet.
Technical vocabularies attempt to control this
polysemy. For example, the structuralist
terminology of language, langue and
parole corresponds to faculty, rules
and acts of expression. These distinctions work
well in considering the relation of system to
performance. They work well in theorizing the
actualization of potentials. They offer points of
departure and arrival.
|
4.40 |
4.41 |
They do not alleviate tendencies to conflate place and
means when language is considered as a medium.
The conflation is inevitable. A place is a
means. Places are prepared. Wisdom of
sacred sites. The uncanny energy of domestic
arrangements. The house of language. The
analogies are potent and have consequences for thinking
language's relation to the body.
|
4.41 |
4.42 |
If language is a tool for the fashioning of self and
the construction of an other, it is the body and its
zones that facilitate the entry into language. Is
the body, this means to an end, a tool? An
instrument upon which the infant plays? A
tantalizing alignment ensues: text as
instrument, text as infant.
|
4.42 |
4.43 |
The jump from language to text through those teasing
unvoiced dentals and their alliteration
(text tantalizing
infant instrument) issues
from the seduction of the signifier. Already the
rearrangement implies text as agent of a pleasurable
irritation, on the infant-instrument, of the infant-
instrument, in the infant-instrument. The
difficulty in ascribing a preposition matches the
difficulty of ascribing agency: the text?
the infant?
|
4.43 |
4.44 |
With Flax is reached the limit of the infant as
patient. With Bordo, the limit of the agency of
the instrument. It is the limit of insertion that
guides Dorothy Smith's discourse. Unlike the
feminists inspired by psychoanalysis, Smith does not
invoke interiorization as a developmental
mechanism. In fact, her standpoint epistemology
is not developmental. However the dynamics of
inside/outside structuration shape her claim for the
suppression of bodily consciousness upon entry into the
"abstracted conceptual mode".
|
4.44 |
4.45 |
Following Marx and Engels, in particular The
German Ideology, Smith relates consciousness to
what people do, not what they are. The social
division of labour places constraints on action and
hence on consciousness. The ways people think
about and express themselves depend upon their
embeddedness in an everyday world. When Smith
grafts phenomenological sociology on to this
materialist base, her analyses shift towards
meditations on spheres of activity. Consciousness
becomes spatialized. One enters a cognitive
mode. As well she also situates both practices of
knowledge production and spheres of activity in a
sexual division of labour.
|
4.45 |
4.46 |
Grossly, her argument depends upon a mapping of private
and public space onto physical and conceptual activity
respectively. This mapping is mediated by an
implicit reading of social reproduction as woman's work
and management or ruling as men's. Women by
analogy are in a position similar to the working class
(n9). The
limits of the analogy remain unexplored. When she
further argues that the arrangement's perpetuation
depends upon its unacknowledgement by those whom it
benefits, that is, the ruling class, her epistemology,
like that of psychoanalytic feminists, hinges upon
repression as a prerequisite for abstract reasoning.
|
4.46 |
4.47 |
Although she makes no explicit reference to the
difference between class consciousness and class
analysis, between knowing one's place in a system and
knowing the system, it is such a distinction that
informs her assessment of material and conceptual
labour as epistemological stances. The values she
assigns are of course informed by considerations of
gender. What she calls acting in the
"abstracted conceptual mode" is associated
with ruling. The physical labour that supports
this mode is "done typically by women" (Smith 1977, 165). The one is
ignorant; the other, all-knowing.
|
4.47 |
4.48 |
Her appeal to Hegel confirms the class-gender-knowledge schema. Drawing on the master-servant narrative in The Phenomenology of Mind, she explains: That organization [of the relation between master and servant] itself is not visible from the standpoint of the master. Within the consciousness of the master there is himself and the object and a servant who is merely a means. For the servant there is the master, the servant's labour producing the object, and there is the simplicity of the relation between the master and the object. The totality of the set of relations is visible. (Smith 1977, 164)
Undoubtedly, Hegel's narrative can be read as depicting
the relation of particular social classes.
However, Hegel does not particularize consciousness in
terms of vision. As a consequence of Smith's
visual idiom, in a move Hegel cannot underwrite,
unmediated experience is poised against a conceptual
mode. Smith states that the "abstracted
conceptual mode of ruling exists in and depends upon a
world known immediately and directly in the bodily
mode" (Smith 1977,
165-166).
|
4.48 |
4.49 |
Oddly, within the perspective of standpoint
epistemology, the bodily mode of knowing appears
centred on a single sensory modality:
sight. Smith links total knowledge to
visibility. This affects her reading of
Hegel. As an automatic consequence of position,
the servant is conscious of the totality of relations
between master and servant. The servant is no
agent. No work is necessary to access
consciousness. This is certainly not what Hegel's
text indicates to be the case. One suspects the
equation of agents to standpoints depends on a possible
confusion in Smith between sensation and perception
thus assigning an unqualified measure of passivity to
sight. Smith seems to forget that most bodies are
conferred locomotion.
|
4.49 |
4.50 |
Standpoints are either points of view or blindspots. The characterization depends upon which world a subject occupies. Smith builds upon a distinction imported from phenomenological sociology: Beginning from the standpoint of women locates a subject in a material and local world. It shows the provinces of meaning described by Schutz not as alternatives a paramount reality on the one hand and the scientific domain on the other but rather as a bifurcation of consciousness, with a world directly experienced from oneself as center (in the body) on the one hand and a world organized in the abstracted conceptual mode, external to the local and particular places of one's bodily existence. (Smith 1977, 169)Why bifurcation? This still keeps two worlds: body vs abstracted conceptual mode, world experienced vs world organized. |
4.50 |
4.51 |
She continues: The abstracted mode of the scientific province is always located in the local and material actualities. Participation in the "head" world is accomplished in actual concrete settings making use of definite material means.(Smith 1977, 169) This poses no problems. Except it suggests a type of nesting almost like that of interiorization. Headwork is done inside a setting. Such a suspicion is not allayed when she continues by moving from many settings to a singular one: Suppression of interest in that setting is organized in a division of labor which accords to others the production and maintenance of the material aspects of a total process. (Smith 1977, 169)
A possible plurality of settings and means is
lost. Without this discursive move the link
between the suppression of interest and division of
labour could not be so strong. The concrete and
abstract would not confront each other across a divide.
|
4.51 |
4.52 |
From the suppression of interest, she argues for the emergence of greater consciousness on the part of those employed in material work: To those who do this work, the local and concrete conditions of the abstracted mode are thematic. But women's standpoint locates a subject in the fundamental "item" of the two fold basis of knowing the world. The organization which divides the two becomes visible from this base. It is not visible from within the other. (Smith 1977, 169) Smith implies rulers are blind to the system as the ruled are not. Somehow the agents get lost. Consciousness is read off structure. To exist as subject and to act in this abstracted mode depends upon an actual work and organization of work by others, who make the concrete, the particular, the bodily, the thematic of their work and who also produce the invisibility of that work. (Smith 1977, 166)
There is no mention in this passage or elsewhere of the
vagaries of exchange value and the participation of the
ruling class in determining comparable worth.
Smith implies that docile labour and self-denial on the
part of those that do material work produce its
invisibility.
|
4.52 |
4.53 |
Oddly, the same qualities of bad faith are applied to the conceptual mode of action. It is a condition of anyone's being able to enter, to become and remain absorbed, in the conceptual mode of action that she does not need to focus her attention on her labors or on her bodily existence. The organization of work and work expectations in managerial and professional circles both constitutes and depends upon the alienation of members of this class from their bodily and local existence. (Smith1977, 166)
One need not dream up golfing doctors and surfing
lawyers to recognize that these circles too are not so
alienated from the body and its impact on job
performance.
|
4.53 |
4.54 |
Replace "conceptual" by "physical" and Smith's account reads like a description of factory work: The structure of work in this mode and the structure of career assume that individuals can sustain a mode of consciousness in which interest in the routine aspects of bodily maintenance is never focal, and can in general be suppressed. It is taken for granted in the organization of this work that such matters are provided for in a way which will not interfere with action and participation in the conceptual mode. (Smith 1977, 166)
Indeed, the whole difference between manual and
intellectual labour collapses.
|
4.54 |
4.55 |
In her later work, the sharp division between abstract and concrete modes inadvertantly limits the permeability of textual zones. Smith's unintended legitimation of the mind-body opposition results from her constitution of text as an implement of a ruling apparatus. In a preface to a collection of essays Smith outlines her project. Again a shift from plural to singular is notable and leaves its imprint on her take on text: Texts are analyzed to display what the subject knows how to do as reader and what the subject knows how to do in reading, and in so doing also displays the organizing capacity of the text, its capacity to operate as a constituent of social relations. (Smith 1990, 5)
In this scheme, text is a site that is entered or an
institution that governs a series of practices.
This rich notion of text is not a matter for
quarrel. However, the syntax here betrays a
one-way movement from text to reader.
|
4.55 |
4.56 |
Smith's uni-directionality neglects the metalinguistic
possibilities of verbal semiosis. Questions about
the boundaries of a text can be elicited from subjects
demonstrating both their know-how in reading and their
ignorance. The handling of a text, especially in
metalinguistic matters, does not always stem from
knowledge. Theories of the text cannot be based
solely on the communicative function of verbal sign
systems. Theory aiming to deconstruct dichotomies
cannot afford to expunge the interpretive
function. Theory making must account for
interstitial spaces.
|
4.56 |
4.57 |
In Flax, Bordo and Smith some form of interiority
operates: an epistemic subject is inserted into a
mode (Smith), the intensity of infant phases is
interiorized and repressed (Flax), it is in
participation that non-Cartesian subjects are immersed
in a world (Bordo). Something is in the subject
or the subject is in something. Mediation slips
out of the picture. A thematics of release scored
for a pas de deux choreographs all movement as motion
away from or towards the other. Liberation
discourses, however, can also imagine repositionings
between other others, in a choreography of an esprit de
corps.
|
4.57 |
4.58 |
Although still performing with dyads, Paul Ricoeur
theorizes what passes between the hermeneutical
players. For him the aim of interpretation is not
to recover access to the mind of an author or the
historical context of an original audience. Its
aim is the disclosure of modes of being-in-the-world,
the revelation of possibilities.
|
4.58 |
4.59 |
Ricoeur characterizes understanding as an act that makes the other, the world projected by a text, one's own. This is appropriation: To understand is not to project oneself into the text; it is to receive an enlarged self from the apprehension of proposed worlds which are the genuine object of interpretation. ("Appropriation" 87) |
4.59 |
4.60 |
The enlargement of self is an increase in potential. Reading gives power. However, the acquisition is not without cost. The acquiring of an "enlarged self" is accomplished by an exchange. Something or rather some part of the reading subject is lost: The reader is rather broadened in his capacity to project himself by receiving a new mode of being from the text itself. Thus appropriation ceases to appear as a kind of possession, as a way of taking hold of...It implies, instead, a moment of dispossession of the narcissistic ego. [...] It is the text with its universal power of unveiling, which gives a self to the ego. (97)
This is a hermeneutics of compulsion. The text
gives. It does not simply
present or offer. The unveiling by the text of a
self or a structure of being cannot be equated with a
reader's acceptance of that self (n10).
Display does not equal the conclusion of barter.
At least this is so if one considers the interaction as
occuring in a market economy. However, for
Ricoeur interpretation culminates in
appropriation. It must. An imperative is
lodged in the indicative. The description is a
prescription. Here, there is no sales
pitch. The very structure of Ricoeurian textual
interaction is shaped by the social obligations of a
gift exchange economy.
|
4.60 |
4.61 |
Economic formulations such as "Reading is an
appropriation-divesture" (95)
recur often in the essay but belie the unidirectional
movement: readers give before they get. In
Ricoeur's discourse there is a strong correlation
between dispossession and emancipation. A text
"can procure new readers for itself" (96)
since in Ricoeur's terms it escapes
from the authorial situation and its original
audience. All evangelism is elided. It is
not a reader or readers who bring readers to a
text. A text, once released into the world,
attracts. Such textual autonomy is required to
cement Ricoeur's analogy between self and text.
|
4.61 |
4.62 |
In proverbial (something lost, something gained) double
entry bookkeeping, Ricoeur tabulates a net gain for
every admission into a textual economy. Loss of
author, gain of readers. Loss of ego, gain of
self. What lends his argument credence is the
disposition. First, gain is accounted from a
text-based perspective; then, that of a reading
subject. As text receives so too the
reader. The analogy remains implicit. If
Ricoeur were to question the parallels constructed
between subject and text, the universal unveiling power
of text would be in need of much particularization.
|
4.62 |
4.63 |
For the link between revelation and appropriation to be
operative the reading subject must be susceptible to
the game of exchange and accumulation. This type
of subject is found implanted in specific
narratives. Ricoeur assigns such a reader two
tasks: growing up and finding a home. These are
the stories respectively of a Freudian and of a
Christian subject. Their stories are found in a
previous Ricoeur collection, The Conflict of
Interpretations.
|
4.63 |
4.64 |
What has become in the essay on appropriation a
vocabulary of Self, in these earlier writings was one
of consciousness. In these essays, the
hermeneutical player is set the task not of
dispossession of the ego but mastery of the libido of
the ego. Mastery evokes maturity and so Ricoeur
expresses the opinion that the question of
consciousness seems to "be bound to the other
question of how a man leaves his childhood behind and
becomes an adult" ("Consciousness and the
Unconscious" 109). Ricoeur's hesitancy
is telling. In the French version (Conflit 110), the phrases
"sortir de l'enfance" and "être en
proie à l'enfance" evoke perhaps more
strongly the design of a release from infancy. It
is a pursuit-and-escape narrative or a story of
temptation overcome that he presents. But Ricoeur
hedges. He does not unequivocally link this
narrative to the question of consciousness.
|
4.64 |
4.65 |
The tentative tone signals his resistance or
ambivalence. At the very moment of advocating
acceptance, submission to the unveiling power of a
text, Ricoeur is challenging the temporal orientation
of psychoanalytic discourse. Ricoeur reverses the
analyst's question. As the translator, Willis
Domingo, stresses, it is the analyst "who shows
man subject to his childhood" ("Consciousness and the
Unconscious" 109). If Ricoeur's
resistance itself is reversible, it is not a prospect
envisaged explicitly.
|
4.65 |
4.66 |
In Ricoeur's account there is no realm of freedom
outside the child-adult pair. For him sublation
is inapplicable to the child-adult dialectic, adulthood
remains an incomplete project. If Ricoeur were to
entertain the negation of a negation, an identity not
child and not adult, the division of age would not be
internal to the subject of enunciation but a function
of the enunciating subject. This location would
expose the child-adult pair to greater
reflexivity. For example, there is a discursive
position free from either end of the telling of a life
story. The listener so-positioned of such a tale
would not, except by accepting a discourse's
invitation, identify with either child or adult.
|
4.66 |
4.67 |
At least two factors destabilize Ricoeur's concept of
appropriation: readers who test the trajectory of
the escape from childhood or narratives which project
modes-of-being and worlds undominated by teleologies of
growing up. Both are hesitant interpretants of
journey narratives couched in a therapy frame, in
particular a frame that situates loss at the beginning
and at the end, gain. Ricoeur's concept of
appropriation rests on his overdetermination of a path
he attributes to Freud.
|
4.67 |
4.68 |
As expressed by Ricoeur, Freud's will is open to limitation. Ricoeur declares that What Freud wants is for the patient to make the meaning which was foreign to him his own and thus enlarge his field of consciousness, live better, and, finally, be a bit freer and, if possible, a bit happier. ("Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Culture" 150)
First, acceptance is independent of revelation.
Second, constant revelation might best be coupled to
some active forgetting, else the reading subject is
bloated with passivity. Finally, at what limit
does expansion no longer coincide with health? On
the way to substituting enlargement of field by
enlargement of self, Ricoeur does not stop to pose the
question. Based on the figure of the analysand,
the reader is pathologized or deemed in need of
instruction. Contra Ricoeur and based on the
figure of the analyst, the reader as therapist offers a
cure for the text. The paradigm case is that of
the critical editor as reader. Such readers are
aware that changes in the materiality of the text
affect the projected world of the work. Ricoeur
assumes a text without variants.
|
4.68 |
4.69 |
With their investments of labour and libido,
analyst-readers offer a basis for pride in
interpretation or at least an assertion of ego in
choice. However Ricoeur's reader in need of
instruction leads to the scenario of the humiliation of
the ego ("Psychoanalysis and
Contemporary Culture" 152-153). It is
not quite clear how Ricoeur attains an ascesis of
denial, figured as the gamble of ego dispossession for
the promise of an enlarged self, from the scene of
analysis's recapitulation of the classic injunction to
know thyself. The clue is perhaps to be found in
the wandering character of such a reader.
|
4.69 |
4.70 |
In the "Preface to Bultmann" Ricoeur writes of Christian hermeneutics: this appropriation [of the Biblical text, of the Christian kerygma] is only the final stage, the last threshold of an understanding which has first been uprooted and moved into an other meaning. (397)
Wandering is the prerequisite to appropriate
appropriation. Closure comes with appropriation
which is the last step of an understanding unsettled in
an alien sense. Even if appropriation is only
remotely a prodigal homecoming, there is no denying
Ricoeur's stress on reorientation. Migrant
readers, nomadic interpreters, have no need of enlarged
selves. The text is not a refuge. It is a
way.
|
4.70 |
4.71 |
One holds a way, one is possessed by it. The way may be a home and search for it, pointless. The game of appropriation, shorn of its home-finding, need not appear as an inexorable cumulation of surplus. Ricoeur's secular formulation of appropriation bears repeating: The reader is rather broadened in his capacity to project himself by receiving a new mode of being from the text itself. Thus appropriation ceases to appear as a kind of possession, as a way of taking hold of... ("Appropriation" 97)
What do those suspension marks mean? They are
those of Ricoeur's text. Indeterminacy? Are
they, these marks, a gesture? Or simply the space
between the event of speech and the written text since
this piece was first presented as a lecture (n11). Are
they to be read as hesitancy, lack of assurance that
appropriate interpretation is a being held, a being
possessed? Or are they not a mode of letting go,
a pause offered for reflection upon the metaphors of
ownership and dispossession?
|
4.71 |
4.72 |
They are, those marks, a hold. They are a space
for the hook of questions. They become only
meaningful through the labour of an interpreter.
Readerly work is possible because texts are
manipulatable and their projected worlds
analysable. Work-centred notions of reading and
especially rereading thrive on recursivity. Their
own workings enter into the play of
interpretation. Not so Ricoeur's model of
appropriation which shares with the models of
interiorization deployed by some feminist
epistemologies a masking of the labourer. For the
former, the labourer is libidinally invested in the
products of interpretation thus incapable of
dispossession of the ego, incapable of appropriation
and understanding. For the latter, the labourer
is of the domain of culture, is an instance of
instrumental reason, a rejection of the mother.
Others arrive at a similar condemnation of instrumental
reason by reinscribing the intellectual and manual
labour distinction onto gender.
|
4.72 |
4.73 |
The alignment, child of psychoanalysis, labourer of
sociology, reader of hermeneutics, is suggested by
their common concern with transformation. And, no
matter the discursive object, from child to reader, the
relation between techne and consciousness pivots on the
key question as to whether the transformer is
transformed. Is the user of tools changed by
their use? Of course to answer such a question
requires the application of critical tools.
|
4.73 |
4.74 |
At a metadiscursive level "tool" and
"question" are apt to become
equivalent. However before "answer" is
made analogous to "consciousness" it must be
recognized that questions solicit addressees as tools
do not. Another angle is possible. Access
to consciousness occurs through language. In
language according to Karl
Bühler's analysis of
the triangulation of communication one addresses
someone about something. Likewise it could be
said one is conscious of something for some
reason. That tool use should transform tool users
unconsciously should not deter one from at arriving at
similar conclusions. As one speaks so one remains
silent vis-à-vis someone about something;
one is unconscious about something for some reason.
|
4.74 |
4.75 |
Whatever the truth-value assigned to the link between
language and consciousness, there exists a structural
homology between the position of
interlocutor in language and that of
reason or motive in acts of
consciousness. For someone, for some reason,
something is said, something is the object of
consciousness.
|
4.75 |
4.76 |
How does a link between tool use and asking questions
relate to reading? First, the analogy is not
between text and tool but between tool use and
reading. A tool-use environment has three
components. They may be described as the tool
proper, the instruction, directives or demonstrations
of tool use and the material on which the tool is
used. Directive and tool are often conflated in
the concept of techniques. Regardless, effects of
transformation should be ascribed to a combination of
proper directives, competent tools and pliable
material.
|
4.76 |
4.77 |
Second, like a tool-use environment, a reading
environment can be composed of three parts.
Sometimes the term "text" covers all
three: instrument, directive and material.
Text can be a tool proper. In the case of Ricoeur
it is a means to access projected worlds and to reveal
modes-of-being. A text can also offer a set of
directives although these may more often belong to the
discourse that takes up a given text. A text
presents material to be worked upon. Reading
presents a case where the relation between techne and
consciousness is potentially recursive.
|
4.77 |
4.78 |
In such situations questions proliferate.
Questions raise questions. In such ways are texts
mined for more than one mode of being. Through
such practices, reading becomes a species of
translation.
|
4.78 |
4.79 |
Elmar Holenstein, drawing on Roman Jakobson's elaboration of information theory's communication model, considers that the code-switching capabilities inherent in metalinguistic function place at the disposal of the interpreter a "whole system of regularly alterable patterns" ("Structure of Understanding" 235). The implications for the encounter with texts prove triumphal: If a situation is structured verbally it can also be reflected. To each linguistic production belongs the possibility of metalinguistic reflection. Every child learns language by relating new expressions to the ones already known and by contrasting them with each other. Each linguistic utterance can be paraphrased, i.e. translated into ever new contexts. ("Structure of Understanding" 236)
Sharing Holenstein's unshakable faith in
translatability, a sceptical interpreter, like a
language learner, will return repeatedly to
metalinguistic reflection in the action of
comparison. There appears to be no end to the
recursive activity of paraphrase, translation or
metalinguistic application.
|
4.79 |
4.80 |
Never ending but not beyond control. The
metalinguistic moment can be self-reflexive and
self-regulating to the extent that it asks about the
parameters of its own applicability. The moment
is curtailed in the reading of texts if
the material presence of an interlocutor is posited as
a prerequisite for triggering metalinguistic
reflection.
|
4.80 |
4.81 |
This is how that quasi-passive acceptance of a world
presented by a text becomes Ricoeur's paradigm case for
reading and interpretation. His discourse bars
transcoding and hence metadiscursive moments. The
resources of the metalinguistic function are lost to
theory and to reading if between oral and graphic
realizations of verbal forms too strong a distinction
is made. For example, Ricoeur sets the
possibility of operating metalinguisticaly solely in
the context of oral contact, reserving hermeneutics for
written expression. He declares
"hermeneutics begins where dialogue ends" (Interpretation
Theory
32). Notwithstanding the
differences between
listening and seeing, in face-to-face communication
cultural codes may block any and all metalinguisitic or
metadiscursive statements. Interlocutors may not
wish to appear rude. Interlocutors may fear
expressing ignorance. Interlocutors may not
possess the competence to frame meta-statements.
Dialogue, oral or written, can find itself
impeded. Ricoeur recognizes this. However,
for him there is no mechanism in the handling of
written texts equivalent to metalinguistic statements
in speech events. He does not to consider such
parallels possible. Rereading remains
untheorized.
|
4.81 |
4.82 |
Other thinkers relying on eye-ear dichotomies also do
not always consider such parallels and inevitably block
consideration of the phenomenon of rereading.
They do however assign it a peculiar place outside
aesthetic experience. For example, although he
also opts for favouring a single sensory mode, Roman
Ingarden in his phenomenology grants a place to
rereading. Unlike Ricoeur, his choice to
privilege hearing involves no necessary humiliation of
the reading subject. Like Ricoeur, a teleological
dimension centres on an individual reader who is to
adopt a proper attitude. In this model literary
works of art are not received via revelation of an
inscribed word. They are fulfilled via
concretization.
|
4.82 |
4.83 |
In Ingarden's aesthetics, the literary work is a
schematic formation which contains places of
indeterminacy. Individual concretizations remove
these places of indeterminacy only partly. Other
concretizations always remain possible. The
literary work is composed of four strata: sound
formations, meanings, represented objects and
schematized aspects of those objects (n12).
Because the first stratum of the literary work of art
is sound formation, the model generates a tendency to
consider (though not explicitly) indeterminacy as
equivalent to silence. But this indeterminacy,
this silence, is not the space for a hook of
questions. According to Ingarden the aesthetic
concretization is disfigured by interrogative
approaches such as rereading.
|
4.83 |
4.84 |
Ingarden's description and not so veiled prescription is based on a dualist typology of texts. Ingarden's literary aesthetics introduce a dichotomy between sonorous aesthetic concretization and visual scientific actualization. His point of departure, the sound formation stratum, correlates with the cognitive attitude and reading practices he deems proper to aesthetic concretization and the realization of aesthetic value. Richard Shusterman explains why Ingarden overlooks the graphic dimension of verbal artefacts: I think part of the explanation is in an unsatisfactory and unnecessarily constrained picture of aesthetic appreciation, one that is too much enclosed in a singular temporally progressive and ephemeral experience of concretization where proper recognition is not sufficiently given to the funding effect and superimposition of previous experience of the work. (Shusterman 145) |
4.84 |
4.85 |
The injunction against rereading is clear in Ingarden's text: Lengthy interruptions in reading, the repetition of certain parts of the work during reading, referring back to parts which have already been read and have sunk into the phenomenal past all this disfigures the aesthetic concretization of the literary work of art and its aesthetic value. (Cognition 165)
The reading habits that disfigure are those that
prolong. They are also those that test.
They relate more to the cognition of a scientific work.
|
4.85 |
4.86 |
Ingarden states that An essential feature of the scientific work is that it is intended to fix, contain, and transmit to others the results of scientific investigation in some area in order to enable scientific research to be continued and developed by its readers. (Cognition 146) Whereas The literary work of art does not serve to further scientific knowledge but to embody in its concretization certain values of a very specific kind, which we usually call "aesthetic" values. It allows these values to appear so that we may see them and also experience them aesthetically, a process that has a certain value in itself. (Cognition 146)
Unlike Smith's abstract and material modes of
cognition, approaches to the scientific work and to the
literary work of art are not reducible one to the
other. Smith's modes both contribute to the same
end: social reproduction. Ingarden's discursive
objects each serve different purposes and intend
different values.
|
4.86 |
4.87 |
Others have engaged Ingarden's ontology of values (n13).
Tempering Ingarden's objectivism, such work stresses
the relational and decisional grounds of values.
In a parallel manner, the enlargement of aesthetic
experience is possible. Activities proscribed by
Ingarden can be admitted.
|
4.87 |
4.88 |
For example rereading is a proper aesthetic
activity. Indeterminacy in Ingarden's model is a
function of incompleteness. Undecidability and
cruxes also play a role in the appearance and
experience of aesthetic values.
|
4.88 |
4.89 |
A brief example will illustrate the need to recast Ingardian concretization if unvoiced textual elements enter the aesthetic experience. A character in Salman Rushdie's novel Shame expresses herself thus: "Who is to understand the brains of those crazy types?" asked Munnee-in-the-middle, in tones of final dismissal. "They read books from left to right." (36)
The tense of "read" is not
indeterminate. It is undecidable. The
consequences are significant. Books with
sentences reading left to right need not themselves be
read continuously from left to right. The
persistence of past practices is a theme of the
novel. Depending on the tense one selects, one
can play with, in this passage, either consonance or
contrapuntal tension between the situation of
enunciation and the subject of enunciation. Both
choices produce an aesthetic value very much in accord
with an Ingardian axiology of harmony. However it
is a value that can only be arrived at through
rereading locally, of the sentence, and globally, of
the book.
|
4.89 |
4.90 |
Rereading prevents the decay of dialectic.
|
4.90 |
4.91 |
Rereading brings one closer to the desiderata of a model for embodied knowing. The model is haptic. The sheet of skin's touch is recursive. It senses itself, the world and its own sensing. Its recursivity like that of language is enhanced by multiple contact and regulated by interplay. When sight and hearing act like touch, a common sense is possible and transcoding can lead to metacommentary. |
4.91 |
© François Lachance, 1996