3.0 - 3.9


Emulations


3.0

Asking a question is akin to telling a story.  Drawing a picture is like telling a story.  Both, drawing pictures and asking questions, are ways of orienting.  Both focus attention.  Of course telling stories is a way of orienting.  The circularity of these assertions depends not upon the equivalency of the products, question, picture, story, but the activities, asking, describing, telling.

3.0

3.1

As ways of orienting, all are moments of a relentless semiosis, all rework representations, all participate in some measure of transcoding.  These ways of doing are readily framed as the potential of an object.  What can be described becomes narratable and open to interrogation;  what is askable has a story.  Actions and objects correlate;  praxis bears on semantics.

3.1

3.2

This slippage between doing and meaning is the central point of Ricoeur's critique of Greimas's narrative grammar.  At stake is the adequacy of transcodings.  Also at stake are the bases of formalization:  permissible degrees of abstraction, legitimate limits to the role of reduction and extrapolation in interpretation.  In short, hermeneutics confronts semiotics over the proper use of tools.

3.2

3.3

Ricoeur expresses reservations about the equivalence of metalanguages and about the conversions that turn an achronic taxonomy of logical relations into the syntactic operations of a narrative structure.  In short Ricoeur is troubled by the generative trajectory traced by Greimas, a trajectory that according to Ricoeur depends upon the mixed nature of its fundamental structure.

3.3

3.4

For Ricoeur, this mixed nature of the model conditions its applicability and so he claims in his concluding statement

to explain to readers of works stemming from this school why the semiotic square sometimes seems to have a true heuristic value, and sometimes to be simple transcription, which can be more or less elucidating but sometimes corresponds to a more or less forced understanding of narrative which proceeds not according to the logical component, but according to the praxico-pathetic component of the mixed model. ("Greimas's Narrative Grammar" 28)

What could be attributed to skill is vested by Ricoeur in the appropriateness of the tool.  However the square is not for Ricoeur just an anthropomorphized error prone machine.  He takes great pains to demonstrate that the machine part, the logical component, cannot alone generate narratives;  a body needs to be imported into the model or must be present from the outset.  Machine and body are not Ricoeur's terms.  In his discourse, logic is set against doing and feeling.  This opposition is temporally figured as the difference between static taxonomy and dynamic narrative.

3.4

3.5

It is through this set-up that Ricoeur reads Greimas.  However, there is a glitch in Ricoeur's motion detection device.  Ricoeur introduces alongside the Greimassian nomenclature two Aristotelian terms, dianoia and mythos ("Greimas's Narrative Grammar" 23) which are said to conform to Greimas's "heterotopic spaces".  In Frye, who is Ricoeur's authority here, the difference between the two Aristotelian terms is related to a division of the senses, a division of labour for the eye and the ear (Anatomy of Criticism 77).  The ear is matched with narrative or mythos; dianoia or meaning, with the eye.  The coupling of this sensory mapping with the dynamic/static binary affects Ricoeur's evaluation of Greimas's model.  In particular, his judgement on its ability to bridge the taxo-narrative hiatus is overdetermined by his yoking of the static with the visual.

3.5

3.6

What A.J. Greimas designates as the elementary structure of signification has come generally to be known as the semiotic square.  Greimas himself does not reduce the elementary structure to its graphic incarnation.  He states that the square is a visual presentation of a relational network ("Entretien" 21).  In an 1984 discussion with Ricoeur, he states that "As to the semiotic square, it could be a square or a cube or a circle.  The shape is of no importance whatsoever.  It was necessary to formulate a minimum number of relational tools, and in this case, a fundamental structure of discourse that was as simple as possible" ("On Narrativity" 554-555).  The two criteria, a minimum number of tools and simplicity, only appear to be unrelated to shape.

3.6

3.7

Certain geometries are precluded from Greimas's list.  His enumeration contains aught but closed figures.  Furthermore each of the closed figures is symmetrical.  The range of choices is not without consequences.

3.7

3.8

Simplicity can be quite complex.  Semiotic formalization, if it is like that of mathematics, attempts to meet Hilbert's three basic requirements:  consistency, completeness, and decidability.  Ricoeur works the tension between completeness and consistency.  His critique retraces the moments where elements are, he claims, added or introduced at each subsequent level of the generative trajectory.  His critique terminates with the declaration that Greimas's point of departure must be heterogeneous.  The model possesses a mixed nature.  One recognizes the dilemma: either incomplete, in need of additions at every stage, or inconsistent, mixed from the outset.

3.8

3.9

Ricoeur wishes to determine the consistency of the procedures that guide the transformation of a semantic binary into a series of narrative utterances.  Ricoeur's critique centres on the satisfactory passage from a static morphology to a dynamic syntax.  It is the temporalization of taxonomy or the narrativization of the fundamental structure of signification that concern him.

3.9


wake bridge prow





© François Lachance, 1996